The definition of life by NASA and this interview that traces its history are symptomatic of the confusion of the thought that claims to be scientific on the general notions and concepts that should be at the basis of the reflection on what are living beings as physical objects, that is to say the very foundations of biology. We propose a critical analysis.
What is life?
It’s a seemingly simple question that leads to complex answers and heated philosophical and scientific arguments. Some focus on metabolism as the key to life, others on genetics, and there has even been a suggestion that we need a whole new field of science in order to come up with a satisfactory definition.
If we ever hope to identify life elsewhere in the universe, we need to understand what separates living creatures from non-living matter. A working definition lately used by NASA is that “life is a self-sustaining system capable of Darwinian evolution.”
[With such a definition, it is not certain that life on Earth really exists!]
This definition is often credited to Gerald Joyce of the Scripps Research Institute. Joyce’s research focuses on the origin of life, and his lab was the first to produce a self-replicating system, composed of RNA enzymes, capable of exponential growth and evolution.
In this interview, Joyce counters the claim that he coined NASA’s working definition of life, and then discusses the history and thinking behind it. He also reveals why it’s been so hard to come up with a definition that encompasses all the aspects and dimensions of life as we know it.
Q: I’ve heard that you created the definition of life currently used by NASA.
A: No, it’s not mine. To explain a little of the history: John Rummel, who was the manager of the NASA Exobiology program at the time, had something called the “Exobiology Discipline Working Group.” [Exobiology seeks to detect life on other planets. Researchers therefore need a definition that allows them to detect it, unlike simple biologists who are content to observe the existence of life on Earth.] It wasn’t a peer-review panel, but rather an advisory group to the program manager on trends and future directions for the field. The panel was made up of 12 people, and it was a very broad group with regard to scientific expertise. I was one member, and the panel chair was Dick Young, who was the first program manager of Exobiology at NASA. He is now deceased. John Rummel wanted us to put together something called the “Discipline Science Plan,” which would give him guidance on directions for the field. So we did that, but it’s not a public document — it was an internal document to help John or the subsequent program managers.
The panel talked at length about the origins, evolution and distribution of life, and somewhere in the discussion we asked, “What about defining life? We keep saying we’re going to look for it, we’re going to try to make it, we’re going to understand how it arose and how it evolves… so what is it?”
That became a topic for discussion, both in the formal sessions and at dinner in the evening. And of course, you can’t rigorously define life because it’s not a scientific term to begin with, it’s a popular term. Even among scientists, trying to treat it as a scientific term, there are different ways to approach it. Some want a list of attributes, others want a fundamental process, others want some physically recognizable set of attributes for detection.
[Life is what animates living beings. What is important, therefore, is not to “define life”, but to determine what a living being is from a scientific point of view, i.e. as a material object. The right question is therefore: what is the specificity of living beings compared to the inanimate objects that physics studies and compared to the machines that this science allows us to build?]
So we realized we’re not going to make a definition. First of all, we shouldn’t be in the business of doing so, but also it isn’t really possible. Yet we felt like there had to be some kind of working definition. The plan document doesn’t say, “The working definition is…” This was just a matter of discussion so we would know what we were pointing towards and talking about.
[But how can we know what we are talking about if we do not propose a definition in conclusion. This is typical of academic research, which seems to be afraid to conclude at the risk of being unemployed!]
There was various language on the table, and I do think I suggested the phrase “self-sustaining chemical system.” But it was all a part of the group discussion. There is a place in the plan document that talks about the emergence of such a system as being tantamount to the origin of life.
All of this happened around 1992. Of course, the structure of DNA was discovered in 1953, and the field was still digesting a more genetics-oriented point of view for life, in contrast to one based purely on chemical flux. So this was a way to take advantage of all the progress that was being made in biology and in understanding the fundamental principles of our biology, but also to try to think more broadly.
The coolest thing in the discussion, which wasn’t in the plan document, was appreciating how Darwinian evolution achieves the key attribute of life, which is to allow complex systems to persist despite an often unpredictable and changing environment. And it does so through molecular memory in the form of genetic information that arises and is maintained by Darwinian evolution.
[By “Darwinian evolution” Gerald Joyce means random genetic mutations and the natural selection of the fittest in the struggle for survival and reproduction. However, it is difficult to understand the link or the shortcut he makes between the “key attribute of life” and genetic “molecular memory”.
Let us recall that the genes carried by the DNA of each living being code for complex proteins that cellular metabolism could not otherwise synthesize on the basis of the simpler biochemical reactions that take place within it.
Gerald Joyce seems to believe – like many biologists at the time (and still today) – that the survival of living beings would be due to a kind of “memorization”, the recording of past experience in an “often unpredictable and changing environment” by natural selection. He thus neglects the adaptive plasticity of living beings because he implicitly has a conception of the living being as a machine: machines only function well in a predictable and stable environment, otherwise they malfunction and go wrong.]
Is there an entirely different way to do that? Not our life, not anything that we’ve ever seen, but perhaps there is another way to skin that cat? That would be a huge breakthrough, if there was some paradigm other than Darwinian evolution that gets you what Darwinian evolution gets you. That was a fun part of the discussion, but of course, no one had a specific alternative, and I’ve never heard anyone make a credible proposal of how to achieve all of that without Darwinian evolution. When we go in search of other forms of life, we need to be thinking about not just chemicals, but how they’re part of a system that has molecular memory and enables Darwinian evolution.
[In the “Darwinian” conception of evolution – in fact, the articulation between natural selection and genetics made during the elaboration of the « synthetic theory of evolution » in the 1930s – the history of living beings is inscribed in the genetic « molecular memory », and nowhere else.
The survival of the living being seems here to depend entirely on this memory. This implies that the behavior of the living being under certain circumstances is also stored in memory, in accordance with the definition of the “genetic program” given for the first time by the American biologist Ernst Mayr (1904-2005) in a single sentence in a scientific paper:
“The completely individualistic and yet also species-specific DNA code of every zygote (fertilized egg cell), which controls the development of the central and peripheral nervous systems, of the sense organs, of the hormones, of the physiology and morphology, is the program for the behavior computer of this individual.”
And he adds afterwards to be clear:
“Natural selection does its best to favor the production of codes guaranteeing behavior that increases fitness. […] The purposive action of an individual, insofar as it is based on the properties of its genetic code, therefore is no more or less purposive than the actions of a computer that has been programmed to respond appropriately to various inputs.”
(“Cause and effect in biology”, Science, vol. 134, n°3489, november 1961)
This implausible statement – which has never been the subject of any experimental verification or scientific discussion, even though the idea of a genetic program has dominated molecular biology for 50 years (and still does today with synthetic biology) – and the conception of the living being that derives from it, according to Gerald Joyce, illustrate above all the denial of the autonomy of the living being in relation to its environment that prevails in the scientific community.]
Now, the reason I get tagged with inventing NASA’s working definition of life is not because I put some language on the table, but because there was a book that David Deamer and Gail Fleischaker edited titled Origins of Life: The Central Concepts. It was published in 1994, and it contains the “greatest hits” of origin of life papers at the time — a collection of classic papers in the field. I was asked to write the foreword. I referred to the working definition in the foreword, and people reference the foreword.
Q: So you were just quoting the collaborative working definition.
A: Yes, and I referred to the Exobiology Discipline Working Group, but of course, that doesn’t exist as a public document, so people instead quote the foreword of the book. And, you know, I still think it is a sensible working definition, and a lot of people in the field think so too. But it’s just a working definition; there’s nothing official about it. Nobody voted on it, even though it reflects a consensus view. The reason it is said to be the “NASA definition” is because it came up in a NASA panel, the Exobiology Discipline Working Group. But NASA doesn’t endorse the definition or use the definition to decide if some funding opportunity is worthy or not worthy, or some research program is successful or not successful. Nothing of the kind.
Q: But doesn’t NASA use the definition to decide what sort of instrumentation to put on rovers, for instance?
A: No, NASA would never weigh the mission against such a simple thing as a working definition. I think what the working definition does is get people’s juices flowing and they say, “Ok, so we can’t just go looking for organic compounds, because they may be biogenic or abiogenic.” What does it mean if they’re biogenic? Well, that means they came from a living process, which according to the working definition means that there’s some Darwinian system that has brought about coded functional molecules that steer the chemistry into biochemistry. So that’s a different way you could put it: the difference between life and non-life is the difference between chemistry and biochemistry. But that’s tautological. What makes biochemistry different from chemistry is that it has history in it, and that history is written in the bits that were deposited through Darwinian evolution. If you think of it that way, it’s a good signpost to guide one’s thinking and for people to challenge each other’s ideas.
[History is reduced to a memory encoded in the DNA. This “guide for thinking” leads especially in the way of a reification of the living being!]
So then you say, “How are you going to look for genetic material if you don’t even know what it is?” If it’s like ours, you might amplify it by PCR (polymerase chain reaction). But what if it’s not like ours? Some might say you should look for some repeating patterns of charges or shapes that are aperiodic and therefore might harbor informational bits.
[The living being is therefore above all a machine for processing information, only capable of generating pre-programmed “adaptive responses” to the different situations it encounters in the environment.]
There are some subtleties in the working definition. It’s not just a Darwinian system. It’s a self-sustaining… chemical system… capable of undergoing… Darwinian evolution. [This term does not appear in the definition that is given at the beginning, and refers very clearly to the machinic conception of the living being that does not write its own history but only undergoes – like any inanimate, inert and dead object – the circumstances.] We actually discussed all those terms. There’s a discussion in the plan document of whether life has to be chemical. Can you have life that is just bits in the aether?
[For Gerald Joyce and his colleagues, life is above all information, not a material process… This is symptomatic of the primacy of the abstract over the concrete in hierarchical societies where leaders dominate those who carry out their orders.]
At that time, artificial life in the computer was a new thing. There’s a statement in the document about how studies of so-called “Alife,” life in the computer, should be encouraged to the extent that they cross-inform studies of chemical life. But NASA’s not expecting to find a bunch of supercomputers on Mars or Titan. Or even PCs or iPhones. So at least for NASA’s purposes, we wanted to focus on chemical life.
[It is curious to note that the “ether” invoked earlier suddenly becomes very material… Life could be in a machine, but it is not a machine.]
“Darwinian evolution” has an associated property list: you can’t have Darwinian evolution without self-replication or reproduction. You can’t have it without mutability, heritability, and variation of form and function. And metabolism is in there too. You can’t have Darwinian evolution without, at some level, a flux of higher-energy starting materials to lower-energy products that drive the processes of replication and whatever is necessary to support replication.
[Metabolism seems here to be reduced to its function of “replication” of DNA, which for Gerald Joyce and his colleagues is the condition for the “reproduction” of the whole living being. Metabolism does not seem to have a role in the maintenance and elaboration of the organization of the living being!]
And then there are the speciality properties like locomotion, irritability, ecological properties such as compartmentalization, and so on; those are all adaptations. And then things like photosynthesis, chemosynthesis, energy storage, and so on; those are just strategies of adaptation. All of that is subsumed by the “Darwinian evolution” part.
[Adaptation is everything in the Darwinian theory that makes living beings into machines, i.e. a system performing various functions.
Gerald Joyce walks on his head by putting evolution before metabolism. The latter is reduced to “adaptation strategies” in the struggle for life; but adaptation to what exactly? As if energy were not the motor of life, that is to say above all of metabolism!
This conception of life conceals the autonomy and the adaptive plasticity due to metabolism. If the living being is dependent on certain elements of the environment for its existence (water, air, food, etc.), this also makes it independent of other elements or circumstances specific to this environment (its nutritional reserves allow mobility or waiting, etc.).
“Darwinian evolution” thus makes it possible not to think of the living being in its specificity and its unity.]
Now let’s describe the “capable” part. It’s the population, or even the ecology, that makes the living system. Capable doesn’t refer to one individual entity; that doesn’t constitute a living system. A single individual might seem to be capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution, but may in fact be dead, or a fossil remnant, or about to die, or unable to find a mate. So it is the system that is said to be capable, not the individual.
[Gerald Joyce forgets the organism in favor of the abstraction of the population. According to the Darwinian theory of evolution – following the elaboration of the “synthetic theory of evolution” in the 1930s – which is based on population genetics, it is above all collections of genes that, by mutating and being selected, generate the evolution of species. The individual organism is therefore (almost) irrelevant to evolution, even though it is the bearer of the life that animates it!
The contortions of Gerald Joyce to give a definition of life without referring to metabolism have therefore also this origin: to bring ignorance about the specificity of the living being into a conception of the evolution of living beings that does not take this specificity into account!]
Then finally “self-sustaining.” That’s the one I think people get most confused about because metabolism is implicit in Darwinian evolution, but not called out in the working definition. People say, “Self-sustained? Nothing’s self-sustained.” But “self-sustained” here refers to only what’s in the rest of the definition. Self-sustained refers to the information necessary to undergo Darwinian evolution. Chemical information is the product of Darwinian evolution. So all of the information necessary for the system to undergo Darwinian evolution must be part of the system.
[Beautiful tautology! Once again, Gerald Joyce relegates the material aspect of the living being to the background to privilege information. In the definition he proposes, metabolism is simply added to “Darwinian evolution”, in order not to forget its material dimension, although it is obviously secondary for him and his colleagues.]
Maybe we should have said, “A chemical system capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution in a self-sustained manner.” But that could still trip people up because they’d say, “It can’t be self-sustained, because that would constitute a perpetual motion machine.”
[This scientist seems to forget that he eats, drinks and breathes every day and that it is to this, and nothing else, that he owes his existence, and not to any informational « perpetual motion ».
This is a denial of the fundamental phenomenon of all living beings, namely assimilation!
The living being is capable of drawing from the environment what it needs to renew its internal organization and ensure its own activity; it is a self-organization of matter which is itself auto-catalytic, which generates itself. The principal characteristic of a living being is therefore that it is “a body which forms its own substance” (Jean-Baptiste Lamarck, Hydrogéologie, Paris, 1802, p. 112) from that which it draws from the environment. The process of assimilation is the fundamental phenomenon, at the root of all other phenomena characterizing living beings, which radically and irreducibly distinguishes living beings from inanimate objects and machines.]
Q: I thought “self-sustained” meant you don’t have to keep pushing it to do it, it does it on its own.
A: It does it on its own in an informational sense [???]. So according to the working definition, a virus doesn’t make the cut. A virus is a chemical system capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution, but if you think of it in terms of a system, a virus isn’t able to undergo self-sustained Darwinian evolution. The viral genome only evolves in the context of the host cell.
Q: The argument I’ve heard against the self-sustained part is that we’re all interdependent.
[Classic confusion between the notions of autonomy, which consists in “giving oneself one’s own rules of conduct” and autarky, “being self-sufficient”. For living beings, autonomy means a certain independence from the conditions of the environment. For example, the bird, like any material object, is subject to the law of gravitation, but it uses the resistance of the air to become independent to a certain extent and go wherever it wants.]
A: Right, but something within the system, within the collective system, must provide all of the information necessary to bring about Darwinian evolution. The virus alone can’t achieve this, but the virus plus the host cell can. Then you have the fact that there are biotechnological tools that enable you to carry out directed evolution. You can evolve RNA in the test tube using biological proteins to copy it, mutate it, and do all those fun things that make it evolve. But it’s not alive because all those tools that you’re using — protein polymerases and so on — were evolved not in the system, and can’t evolve in the system. They were evolved in viruses, bacteria, eukaryotes, and then were co-opted as “information for free” to bring about Darwinian processes. Those informational tools are not subject to the rules of the same game. That’s the key concept: that all of the information necessary for a collective system to undergo Darwinian evolution must be present within the collective system. There’s not a puppeteer that handles all the information offstage, and then the molecules are just the puppet show. You could count the puppeteer as part of the system, but then the puppeteer also has to be evolving. So it’s pretty tricky. I find that a good way to avoid confusion is to ask yourself: where are the bits of information? If you’re talking Darwinian evolution, then you’re talking molecular information. Are the bits in the system or outside the system? If all the bits necessary for the system to evolve are in the system, then it can meet the working definition.
[Repetition of the same tautology as before! This gibberish can only be understood when one admits the postulate that “molecular information” is the whole of the living being and that metabolism has nothing to do with the life that animates it. If the living being is a machine, it needs a “creator” or a “puppeteer”, an information that “shapes” it from outside (here by natural selection)…]
Q: Do you feel the working definition has been helpful to NASA?
A: You’d have to ask John Rummel or Mary Voytek, but I think so. We’ve had this era — which seems to be over now — where different points of view became rivalrous. “It has to be metabolism before genetics.” “No, it has to be genetics before metabolism.” And maybe the working definition for awhile made that worse. But I like to think it now makes it better by providing a common reference point.
Q: Well, we still haven’t found life elsewhere, so it’s necessary to have some definition to help us do that.
A: Scientists are getting quite close in the lab, I think. My own lab has developed a self-sustained chemical system capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution. All of the bits that are necessary for it to evolve are within the evolving system. So why isn’t that life? Well, there’s a little more to it, I think, which has to do with the “capable” part. We really need to expand that part of the working definition. Our laboratory system is capable of evolving, but thus far it has not evolved any new functions.
So then you come back to: why is Darwinian evolution put front and center in thinking about life? Because it is a way for complex entities to maintain themselves, not as an individual but as a system, in the face of a changing environment that is subject to unanticipated change. A system evolves to adapt to environmental change. It has to be able to invent new functions because those environmental changes may be more than incremental. But that gets you on a slippery slope of: how “capable” must it be before we regard it as “capable”? Compare something that evolved for 40 minutes and was never heard from again, versus something that evolved for 40 million years and was never heard from again because a giant impactor took it out. So the threshold for “capable” gets a little tricky.
Q: I thought the “capable” was a way to get away from “exhibiting” evolution. Because it would be hard to say whether something you’re looking at in the field is currently undergoing evolution.
A: That’s exactly why “capable” was put in the working definition. But how capable is what I’m now getting at. Capable of fiddling with the 3rd or 4th decimal place of a particular attribute? Some people want to say “capable of open-ended Darwinian evolution.” But “open-ended” is too much because life on Earth isn’t completely open-ended. If Earth were to be struck by a really massive impactor, life would be over here. So life is not open-ended to all possible events. I think “broadly pluripotential” is the right phrase, but I don’t think that will be made part of the working definition. How “broad” is “broadly.” Lots of things can change in the environment, within some set of bounds, and the system can withstand those changes and, in a Darwinian sense, can survive. I don’t think you can do much better than the present working definition without getting into relative terms.
[It is quite possible to do much better than this definition if we start from the reality of living beings, and not from the confused ideas accumulated in two centuries of biology…
But for that, it would be necessary to start by understanding metabolism a little and then go on to evolution. Indeed, the history of living beings (evolution) is a consequence of the autonomous activity of living beings (which their metabolism confers). Gerald Joyce and his colleagues are walking on their heads by starting from a preconceived idea of evolution (which does not take into account metabolism) and then trying to define what living beings are (as adaptive machines subject to the constraints of the environment).]
Q: But there’s no definition for life that is currently agreed upon by everyone. Is that because scientists have different research focuses, and therefore have differing ideas of what is most important?
A: It’s part of that. But people have different philosophical point of views, too, of what is and what is not important. Some people say genetics is just a strategy bring about the flux of higher-energy starting materials to lower-energy products. Some would say genetics is a kind of adaptation itself. I wouldn’t say that because, to me, genetics is the fundamental basis for Darwinian evolution.
I think of it in terms of the following: what makes biology different compared to chemistry is that biology has a history. That history begins when Darwinian evolution begins, and each next page in that history book is each successive generation and all the genotypes it contains. Chemistry isn’t like that. Chemistry doesn’t record itself, it just happens.
[Once again, history is reduced to a memory. Gerald Joyce forgets in passing that the chemistry of living beings, biochemistry, is not simply linear, but is made up of cyclical processes.
And so, in fact, “chemistry is not recorded” in a memory, it is on the contrary a real history that repeats itself through biochemical cycles that endure and evolve within the metabolism. Gerald Joyce seems to ignore that what is transmitted through generations is not only the genetic material (DNA), but also the biochemical processes of metabolism that allow its translation into proteins and thus the maintenance and elaboration of the organization of the living being as a whole.]
Some say that Darwinian evolution itself is nothing more than a chemical system. But for me that’s odd to say, because once the system is capable of Darwinian evolution, it’s no longer just a chemical system. It has historical attributes and therefore, by definition, it is biological.
[Like many biologists obsessed with DNA and information, Gerald Joyce forgets that there is a continuity of biochemical processes across generations. And that this continuity draws a real history – the evolution of species – through the historical construction of living beings: in the course of evolution, they develop “diversified organs and more eminent faculties” (Lamarck); adaptive diversification and complexification of the organization of living beings.]
Q: That almost sounds like a definition: Life is chemistry with a history.
A: That’s pretty good — I like that! But you can’t put that forward as a working definition because people would go nuts. They’d say there are all sorts of chemical systems that go through oscillations, chaotic behavior, and non-retraceable trajectories. Those systems have a history, but not molecular memory. You can get contingent history in complex chemical systems as a consequence of particular reaction trajectories.
But biology is different in that it actually records the history. Like a palimpsest, a document that’s written on again and again and again, biology is a record of what has proven adaptive at the time, time after time after time. It’s a really powerful way to organize matter.
Gerald F. Joyce, M.D., Ph.D., is a professor and investigator in the Skaggs Institute for Chemical Biology at the Scripps Research Institute.
Defining Life: Q&A with Scientist Gerald Joyce
by Leslie Mullen published on Space.com, August 1, 2013
Concluding remarks
In our opinion, this interview illustrates what Gérard N. Amzallag describes as the era of post-knowledge:
“By losing its hypothetical character to become an unshakeable dogma, the dominant theory takes on the appearance of a myth. Far from constituting an epistemological handicap, this dynamic is revalorized by the emergence of a new scientific horizon, that of the era of post-knowledge. Science then enters a phase of conformism of thought, that of the scientifically correct, from which it becomes very difficult to accuse scientists of conscious fraud. Indeed, in the absence of any theoretical alternative, the results must be interpreted within the metaphysical framework that defines their science, even if it means leaving aside any inexplicable phenomenon.” (Gérard N. Amzallag, La Raison malmenée, p. 132)
Even the simple observable reality and the lived experience of the living beings that we all are!
Gerald Joyce thus exposes in all candor the idealist (and not materialist) conception of the living being which currently dominates in the scientific milieu. Idealist in a double sense, that is to say on the one hand as it promotes a vision of the living being as an informational machine, comparable to the most perfected machines produced by the industrial society today, namely computers, and on the other hand as a set of confused ideas accumulated on the living beings since two centuries, in particular concerning genetics (metabolism governed by a “program”) and evolution (“adaptation” by natural selection as the only historical content, accumulation of anecdotes).
In so doing, he shows the incoherence and absurdity of the current conception of life; at least for those whose brains are not cluttered by this system of preconceived ideas and received as an unquestionable dogma. This ideology is unfortunately all too widespread, and it participates in this project of domination of nature and humans which is at the foundation of industrial capitalism and which is the source of the current ecological and social disaster.
It seems necessary to us to fight this ideology to oppose its deadly consequences and to try to open the way to other conceptions and practices…
Bertrand Louart, July 2022.
Bertrand Louart is a woodworker
in a French cooperative farm of Longo maï.
He is the author of
Living beings are not machines,
La Lenteur, 2018.